the only sanction for the enforcement of collective responsibility is the “pressure of public opinion”

IN THE SUPREME COURT OF INDIA

CRIMINAL ORIGINAL/CIVIL APPELLATE JURISDICTION

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO. 113 OF 2016

KAUSHAL KISHOR                                             … PETITIONER(S)

VERSUS

STATE OF UTTAR PRADESH & ORS. …RESPONDENT(S)

WITH

SPECIAL LEAVE PETITION @ (DIARY) NO. 34629 OF 2017

J U D G M E N T

V. RAMASUBRAMANIAN, J.

 

3. Thereafter,   the   Constitution   Bench,   by   an   order   dated

24.10.2019, formulated the following five questions to be decided by

this Court:­

“…1)   Are   the   grounds   specified   in   Article   19(2)   in

relation to which reasonable restrictions on the right

to free speech can be imposed by law, exhaustive, or

can restrictions on the right to free speech be imposed

on grounds not found in Article 19(2) by invoking other

fundamental rights? 

2) Can a fundamental right under Article 19 or 21 of

the Constitution of India be claimed other than against

the ‘State’ or its instrumentalities? 

3) Whether the State is under a duty to affirmatively

protect the rights of a citizen under Article 21 of the

Constitution   of   India   even   against   a   threat   to   the

liberty of a citizen by the acts or omissions of another

citizen or private agency? 

4) Can a statement made by a Minister, traceable to

any affairs of State or for protecting the Government,

be   attributed   vicariously   to   the   Government   itself,

especially   in   view   of   the   principle   of   Collective

Responsibility? 

5) Whether a statement  by a  Minister, inconsistent

with the rights of a citizen under Part Three of the

Constitution,   constitutes   a   violation   of   such

constitutional   rights   and   is   actionable   as

‘Constitutional Tort”? …”

 

.....

 112. The expression “collective responsibility” can be traced to some

extent, to Article 75(3) insofar as the Union is concerned and to

Article 164(2) insofar as the States are concerned. But in both the

Articles,   it   is   the   Council   of   Ministers   who   are   stated   to   be

collectively   responsible   to   the   House   of   the   People/Legislative

Assembly of the State. Generally collective responsibility of the

Council of Ministers either to the House of the People or to the

Assembly   should  be  understood  to   correlate  to  the  decisions

and   actions   of   the   Council   of   Ministers   and   not   to   every

statement made by every individual Minister.

113. In  State   of   Karnataka  vs.  Union   of   India.108

,  a   Seven

Member   Constitution   Bench   of   this   Court,   while   dealing   with   a

challenge made by the State of Karnataka in the form of a civil suit

under Article 131, to the appointment by the Central Government, of

a commission of enquiry against the Chief Minister of Karnataka,

had an occasion to consider the exposition of the words “collective

108 (1977) 4 SCC 608

139

responsibility”   appearing   in   Article   164(2).   After   indicating   that

collective   responsibility   is   basically   political   in   origin   and

mode of operation, Beg, C.J. opined in the said case as follows:

“46. The   object   of   collective   responsibility   is   to

make   the   whole   body   of   persons   holding

Ministerial   office   collectively,   or,   if   one  may   so

put   it,  “vicariously”   responsible  for  such  acts  of

the   others   as   are   referable   to   their   collective

volition so that, even if an individual may not be

personally   responsible   for   it,   yet,   he   will   be

deemed to share the responsibility with those who

may have actually committed some wrong. …

47. Each Minister can be and is separately responsible

for his own decisions and acts and omissions also.

But, inasmuch as the Council of Ministers is able to

stay in office only so long as it commands the support

and   confidence   of   a   majority   of   members   of   the

Legislature of the State, the whole Council of Ministers

must   be   held   to   be   politically   responsible   for   the

decisions and policies of each of the Ministers and of

his department which could be presumed to have the

support   of   the   whole   Ministry.   Hence,   the   whole

Ministry will, at least on issues involving matters of

policy, have to be treated as one entity so far as its

answerability to the Legislative Assembly representing

the electors is concerned. This is the meaning of the

principle underlying Article 164(2) of the Constitution.

The purpose of this provision is not to find out facts or

to   establish   the   actual   responsibility   of   a   Chief

Minister   or   any   other   Minister   or   Ministers   for

particular decisions or Governmental acts. That can be

more suitably done, when wrongful acts or decisions

are complained of, by means of inquiries under the

Act.   As   already   indicated   above,   the   procedure   of

Parliamentary Committees to inquire into every legally

or ethically wrong act was found to be unsatisfactory

and unsound. The principle of individual as well as

140

collective   ministerial   responsibility   can   work   most

efficiently only when cases requiring proper sifting and

evaluation   of   evidence   and   discussion   of   questions

involved have taken place, where this is required, in

proceedings   before   a   Commission   appointed   under

Section 3 of the Act.

48. Text­book   writers   on   Constitutional   Law   have

indicated   how   collective   ministerial   responsibility   to

Parliament, which has essentially a political purpose

and   effects,   developed   later   than   individual

responsibility   of   Ministers   to   Parliament   which   was

also political in origin and operation. It is true that an

individual   Minister   could,   in   England,   where   the

principle of individual and collective responsibility of

Ministers   was   evolved,   be   responsible   either   for

wrongful acts done by him without the authority of the

whole cabinet or of the monarch to support them, or

under orders of the King who could, in the eye of law,

do no wrong. But, apart from an impeachment, which

has become obsolete, or punishment for contempts of

a   House,   which   constitute   only   a   limited   kind   of

offences, the Parliament does not punish the offender.

For establishing his legal liability recourse to ordinary

courts of law is indispensable.”

114. Quoting from Wade and Phillips on Constitutional Law, this

Court   pointed   out   in   the  State   of   Karnataka  (supra)  that

“responsibility to Parliament only means that the Minster may

be compelled by convention to resign.”

115. The extent to which the enforcement of collective responsibility

can be taken was also indicated in the above decision as follows:

“50. The   whole   question   of   responsibility   is

related   to   the   continuance   of   a   Minister   or   a

141

Government   in   office.   A   Minister's   own   acts   or

omissions or those of others in the department in

his   charge,   for   which   he   may   feel   morally

responsible,   or,   for   which   others  may   hold   him

morally responsible, may compel him to resign. By

an   extension   of   this   logic,   applied   to   individual

Ministers at first, emerged the principle of “collective

responsibility” which we find enacted in Articles 75(2)

and 164(2) of our Constitution. The only sanction for

its   enforcement   is   the   pressure   of   public   opinion

expressed   particularly   in   terms   of   withdrawal   of

political   support   by   members   of   Parliament   or   the

State Legislature as the case may be.”

116. In other words, this Court indicated that while a Minister may

be   compelled   to   resign   for   his   individual   acts   of   omission   or

commission, the only sanction for the enforcement of collective

responsibility is the “pressure of public opinion”.